ON A CONSERVATIVE BAYESIAN METHOD OF INFERRING EXTINCTION
term that is a simple frequency instead of an agnostically varied free parameter. Finally, the assumptions of the method may seem confus- ing, and readers may specifically object to such ideas as only using the information up to a certain interval to compute a posterior for that interval. Only the first point has any practical consequences, the others being philosophical quibbles, so in this paper I will focus on it. A simple, recently published method (Alroy
2015) sidesteps these concerns and could hardly be more different from CSD. The purpose of the present paper is to document this new method’s behavior using simulations. No claim is made that greater accuracy is obtained with this approach, but readers might consider it as a viable and elegant alternative for studying either individual sighting records or sets of records. Potential applications include inferring historical extinction dates from museum specimen records (Burgman et al. 1995; Alroy 2015), testing for simulta- neous extinctions in the fossil record (Marshall and Ward 1996), and possibly even fixing first appearance dates for clades (Marshall 1999).
Method Let D be a string of sighting and nonsighting
records of a single species that are binned into discrete intervals, let P(E) be the prior prob- ability of extinction, and suppose that P(E)is 0.5 (one could also assume it varies uniformly over a range from 0 to 1, but in this paper I sidestep the issue because simulations demon- strate that it makes no practical difference). By Bayes’s theorem, the posterior chance of extinction is:
PðEjDÞ= PðEÞPðDjEÞ +PðAÞPðDjAÞ PðEÞPðDjEÞ (1)
where P(E|D) = the posterior probability of extinction given the data, P(A) is the prior probability of survival (i.e., 1−P(E)), and P(D|E) and P(D|A) respectively equal the conditional probability of the data given extinction or survival. Alternatively,
PðEjDÞ=1PðAÞPðDjAÞ +PðEÞPðDjEÞ PðAÞPðDjAÞ (2)
671 For consistency with Alroy (2014), the P(E|D)
value for each interval is notated as ε later on. Suppose P(E) is uniformly distributed across
intervals, meaning that each one shares a “slice” of this probability that is the same, and suppose that each interval i has its own separate conditional probability P(D|Ei). The product P(E) P(D|Ei) must be zero for all intervals through the one including the last sighting (L) because we know the extinction hypothesis is false during this time interval. We can then reformat equation (2) (Alroy 2015):
PðEjDÞ =1 PðAÞPðDjAÞ
PðAÞPðDjAÞ + P N
i=L+ 1 PðEiÞPðDjEiÞ Now all we need to do is plug in the
conditionals. These could be computed in various ways, for example, by finding the binomial probability of the data given a sampling probability that could be estimated as the frequency of presences within the species’ known range of existence. However, a simple and clean method is to use combina- torics to find the chance that all of the n sightings are jammed into the range from 1 through L given that there areNintervals and that the species survived until i or (if it is alive) through N. Goodman (1952: 627) provided a good way to calculate such conditionals:
PðDjEiÞ=
L1 n1
i1 n
(4) On a minor point, also note that we write
i-1 instead of i (as in Goodman [1952] and Höhle and Held [2006]) because extinction is assumed here to have occurred at the base of interval i, not the top. In other words, i is the first interval during which the species is extinct, not the last during which it is alive. Trivially, the conditional probability given that a species is alive is:
PðDjAÞ=
L1 n1
N n
(5) (3)
Page 1 |
Page 2 |
Page 3 |
Page 4 |
Page 5 |
Page 6 |
Page 7 |
Page 8 |
Page 9 |
Page 10 |
Page 11 |
Page 12 |
Page 13 |
Page 14 |
Page 15 |
Page 16 |
Page 17 |
Page 18 |
Page 19 |
Page 20 |
Page 21 |
Page 22 |
Page 23 |
Page 24 |
Page 25 |
Page 26 |
Page 27 |
Page 28 |
Page 29 |
Page 30 |
Page 31 |
Page 32 |
Page 33 |
Page 34 |
Page 35 |
Page 36 |
Page 37 |
Page 38 |
Page 39 |
Page 40 |
Page 41 |
Page 42 |
Page 43 |
Page 44 |
Page 45 |
Page 46 |
Page 47 |
Page 48 |
Page 49 |
Page 50 |
Page 51 |
Page 52 |
Page 53 |
Page 54 |
Page 55 |
Page 56 |
Page 57 |
Page 58 |
Page 59 |
Page 60 |
Page 61 |
Page 62 |
Page 63 |
Page 64 |
Page 65 |
Page 66 |
Page 67 |
Page 68 |
Page 69 |
Page 70 |
Page 71 |
Page 72 |
Page 73 |
Page 74 |
Page 75 |
Page 76 |
Page 77 |
Page 78 |
Page 79 |
Page 80 |
Page 81 |
Page 82 |
Page 83 |
Page 84 |
Page 85 |
Page 86 |
Page 87 |
Page 88 |
Page 89 |
Page 90 |
Page 91 |
Page 92 |
Page 93 |
Page 94 |
Page 95 |
Page 96 |
Page 97 |
Page 98 |
Page 99 |
Page 100 |
Page 101 |
Page 102 |
Page 103 |
Page 104 |
Page 105 |
Page 106 |
Page 107 |
Page 108 |
Page 109 |
Page 110 |
Page 111 |
Page 112 |
Page 113 |
Page 114 |
Page 115 |
Page 116 |
Page 117 |
Page 118 |
Page 119 |
Page 120 |
Page 121 |
Page 122 |
Page 123 |
Page 124 |
Page 125 |
Page 126 |
Page 127 |
Page 128 |
Page 129 |
Page 130 |
Page 131 |
Page 132 |
Page 133 |
Page 134 |
Page 135 |
Page 136 |
Page 137 |
Page 138 |
Page 139 |
Page 140 |
Page 141 |
Page 142 |
Page 143 |
Page 144 |
Page 145 |
Page 146 |
Page 147 |
Page 148 |
Page 149 |
Page 150 |
Page 151 |
Page 152 |
Page 153 |
Page 154 |
Page 155 |
Page 156 |
Page 157 |
Page 158 |
Page 159 |
Page 160 |
Page 161 |
Page 162 |
Page 163 |
Page 164 |
Page 165 |
Page 166 |
Page 167 |
Page 168 |
Page 169 |
Page 170 |
Page 171 |
Page 172 |
Page 173 |
Page 174 |
Page 175 |
Page 176 |
Page 177 |
Page 178 |
Page 179 |
Page 180 |
Page 181 |
Page 182 |
Page 183 |
Page 184 |
Page 185 |
Page 186 |
Page 187 |
Page 188 |
Page 189 |
Page 190 |
Page 191 |
Page 192